Entries Tagged 'Puzzle' ↓

A curious recursive sequence

Consider the following sequence. Let the first element be \(a_0 = 0\).
Then, for \(a_i\), when \(i>0\), let’s do the following. Consider the last element \(a_{i-1}\). Did this element appear previously in the sequence? If not (meaning that \(a_{i-1}\) is its first occurrence), set \(a_i\) to \(0\). If \(a_{i-1}\) did appear before, then let \(a_k\) be its previous occurrence. Set \(a_i\) to the value \(i-1-k\) (meaning, “how far back did we see this value?”).

So, we have 0,0,1,0,2,0,2,2,1,6,…

For example, the last 6 is there because the previous element 1 has appeared 6 positions earlier.

This is known as Van Eck’s sequence and appears as A181391 in the wonderful On-line encyclopedia of integer seqences. It has been added to OEIS by Jan Ritsema van Eck in 2010. There are many interesting properties of this sequence (for instance, it was shown that it contains infinitely many zeros), and even more intriguing open questions. For more details see the OEIS entry, or these slides by OEIS founder N.J.A. Sloane.

Here is a variation on the above sequence:
Instead of counting the “number of elements”, let’s count only the “number of distinct elements”. That is, again we start with 0, and then if the last element was new, we write 0, otherwise we write “how many distinct elements” have we seen since its previous appearance.

So the sequence goes: 0,0,1,0,2,0,2,2,1,3,…

For example, the last 3 is there because between the previous element 1 and its last appearance there are 3 distinct elements: 0,1,2.

I thought of this sequence independently, but searching for it on OEIS I found that it has been considered before by Nathaniel Shar, who added it to the OEIS as A268755. See here for a plot.

The rule for defining the sequence is similar to the concept of “working set” in the theory of data structures, which refers exactly to the number of distinct queries seen since the previous occurrence of the last query. Therefore, I think a fitting name for the sequence would be “working set sequence”.

So what can we say about the working set sequence (a.k.a. Shar’s sequence)? Does it also contain an infinite number of zeros, similarly to the Van Eck’s sequence? I generated about half a million elements by computer, and the answer seems yes. It could happen, of course, that at some point the sequence reaches a cycle that it can never escape, such as 1,1,1,1,1,… or the less trivial …,1,2,3,3,1,3,2,3,2,2,1,3,3,… (exercise: check that this is really a cycle!)

However, the computer experiment suggests that this does not happen, and eventually every positive integer appears in the sequence.

Can this be proven formally? Yes! Let’s leave this as an exercise (I added a proof sketch to the OEIS entry). As a hint, an easier property to observe is that \(k\) can appear only after \(0,…,k-1\) have already appeared.

Theorem. The working set sequence contains infinitely many zeros.

Zeros seem to appear much less frequently in the working set sequence than in Van Eck’s sequence. But how frequent are they? Empirically it seems that there is a gap of roughly a constant times \(k\) between the \(k\)th and \(k+1\)th zeros, although nothing like this has been proven. Also, the zeros often come in pairs: if, for a long time there have been no new elements, eventually the new element \(k\) comes, followed by \(0\), and then, since \(0\) has also not appeared for a very long time, there is high chance that \(k+1,0\) follow right away. This seems to be the case quite frequently. Overall, however, nothing seems to be known about the statistics of this sequence, e.g. the asymptotic growth rate of \(a_n\).

The indices of new elements in the working set sequence (or alternatively, the indices of zeros minus one) have been added to OEIS as A275668.

I mentioned above two possible cycles in the sequence (although they don’t actually appear if we start from 0). What is the set of all possible cycles, does it have a nice characterization? How many different cycles are there with \(k\) distinct elements? These questions are open.

Finally, another open question about the working set sequence (as far as I know, the same question is open for the Van Eck’s sequence as well):

Problem. Does every pair of nonnegative integers (a,b) eventually appear in the working set sequence as a pair of consecutive elements? (except for (1,1) of course, which cannot appear).

[NOTE added August 2017] As pointed out by Jan Ritsema van Eck in a comment (see below), the Van Eck sequence also excludes pairs of the type (p,p+1). Prove it as a fun exercise, it is not difficult! So let’s modify the conjecture to also exclude (p,p+1) pairs besides (1,1). The conjecture doesn’t seem extremely plausible to be honest (as Jan points out, there are weaker statements one should prove first), so let’s formulate it as a challenge, to move things forward. Can you find an (a,b) pair not of the form (p,p+1) and not (1,1) that does not appear in the van Eck sequence A181391?

This observation does not apply to the working set sequence. For example, (4,5) appears at positions (21,22). So the similar challenge is: Can you find an (a,b) pair other than (1,1) that does not appear in the working set sequence A268755?

A recursive memory game

I made a small logic game/puzzle called Recursi. It consists of independent “memory” games with two pairs of cards each. These games are nested recursively, behind each game there is a card of the game at a higher level. If you find two pairs, you get to flip the card at a higher level behind the current game. Sounds like fun? :) Go ahead and try it. Recursi, a fractal memory game.

A puzzle of apples and oranges

I first read the following wonderful little puzzle on Mathoverflow, where it was posted by David Futer. I don’t know who invented it or where it appeared first – if you have any information, please let me know. (Note: Toshihiro Shimizu points out the following link: AoPS)

There are 99 bags, each containing some number of oranges and some number of apples (any of these numbers can be zero). Show that we can always select 50 bags out of the 99, such that these 50 bags together will contain at least half of all the apples and at least half of all the oranges.

I like this puzzle because there are many different ways to solve it. Before reading on, do yourself a favor and try solving it yourself – it is not difficult, but very rewarding. If you find a proof that is different from those below, let me know and I’ll add it to the list.

——

Why look for different solutions, once we already have one? Partly because it’s fun, partly because each solution might give some new insight into the problem, partly because we can showcase different mathematical techniques, and perhaps most importantly, because each new proof lends itself to generalization slightly differently – so a new proof might lead to new results. The proofs below are sketchy in places, in order to keep them short – it can be instructive to try to fill in the gaps, or to try coming up with the proof after reading just the name of the technique.

Sometimes proving a more general statement is easier (at least psychologically – by removing distracting elements). In our case, it will be more “fruitful” to prove the following statement:

Given \(n\) bags that contain oranges and apples, we can select \( \lceil \frac{n+1}{2} \rceil \) bags such that they contain at least half of each type of fruit. (we only really care about the case when \(n\) is odd)

Here are all the proofs that I am aware of.

Proof 1. (sorting) (source: I vaguely recall seeing this proof on a math competition website but I can’t find it anymore. If you have any information, please let me know see AoPS link above).

Sort the \(n\) bags in decreasing order of the number of apples (break ties arbitrarily). Select the first bag, and from each following consecutive pair select the one with more oranges (break ties arbitrarily).
It is easy to see that the selected bags satisfy the required properties.

Proof 2. (induction) (source: idea from David Futer).

First we show that for \( n=3 \) the statement is true. Indeed, we can select the bag with the most apples and the one with the most oranges (if the two are the same, we also pick another bag).
Assume that the statement is true for \(n-2\). We then prove it for \(n\):
Consider a “good split” of the \(n-2\) bags into A and B, such that A has at least half of both fruits in A+B (such a split exists by the induction assumption). Now we try adding the other two bags, x and y.
If A has as many of both fruits as B+x or as B+y, we are done (we add the other bag to A).
Otherwise if B+x or B+y have as many of both fruits as A, we are done (we add both bags to B).
Otherwise if A has less apples than B+x and less apples than B+y we are done (add to A the one of x and y with more apples). Symmetric argument for oranges.
Otherwise if A has less apples than B+x and less oranges than B+y, it means that A has less of both fruits than B+x+y, which we treated already. Symmetric argument after swapping the terms “apples” and “oranges”. There are no other cases.

Proof 3. (contradiction or “canonical counter-example”)

Suppose there is no solution, then consider a set of \( \frac{n+1}{2} \) bags which has at least half of the apples (there is always such a set), and among such sets the one with the most oranges possible.
Let this set be A, and the remaining set B (A has at least half of apples and B has more than half of oranges).
Take the bag from A with the least oranges and move it to B. Now take the bag from B with the most oranges and move it to A. If we just moved the same bag back, it means that all bags originally in B have at most as many oranges as the bag with the least oranges in A. This contradicts the fact that B has more than half of all oranges.
Otherwise there are two cases: 1) the number of apples in A drops below half when we move a bag, which means that B becomes a solution, or 2) the number of apples in A remains at least half throughout, then after the swap we increased the number of oranges in A, which contradicts the statement that the chosen set had the highest such value.

Proof 4. (counting) (source: I read this proof written in probabilistic form by Erez Druk, after being asked by Dror Ozeri on a puzzle forum – as it is a closed forum, I cannot link to it)

I write this and the next proof in the n=99 case only, to avoid excessive notation. The number of 50-sets of bags is the same as the number of 49-sets \({99 \choose 49}\). Denote the number of 50-sets that contain at least half of all oranges by \(N_{50}\), and the number of 49-sets that contain at least half of all oranges by \(N_{49}\). We have \(N_{50}>N_{49}\), unless none of the bags contain any oranges, which is an easy case anyway (there is one-to-one mapping from 50-sets to 49-sets, such that each 50-set contains its mapped 49-set). Clearly, more than half of all 50-sets contain at least half of all oranges (otherwise the previous inequality would be violated: if an 50-set does not contain at least half of all oranges, then its complementing 49-set does).
The same argument holds for apples. As more than half of the 50-sets contain at least half of the oranges, and more than half of the 50-sets contain at least half of the apples, there is at least one 50-set containing at least half of both fruits.

Proof 5. (price function) (source: from David Futer)

Assign price \(x\) to an orange, and \(1-x\) to an apple. Select the 50 most expensive bags.
Denote:
\(f(x) = (\mbox{# of oranges in top 50}) / (\mbox{total # of oranges})\)
\(g(x) = (\mbox{# of apples in top 50}) / (\mbox{total # of apples})\)

We have \(g(0) \geq 1/2, f(1) \geq 1/2\), and \(f\) is increasing, \(g\) is decreasing. Clearly there is some \(x\) for which both \(f\) and \(g\) are at least 1/2, which denotes a solution (if for some \(x\) both functions would have values below 1/2, then the top 50 would not be the top 50, as its complement would have more apples and more oranges, therefore higher total price).

Proof 6. (geometry – Ham-Sandwich) (source: from David Futer, and a variant explained by Dror Ozeri on the same forum)

We represent the bags as sets in the plane, with the restriction that a straight line can cross at most two of them (this can always be achieved). We somehow encode the number of oranges and apples in each bag. There are more possible variants here: map each fruit to a red or blue point (depending on its type); or map all oranges of a bag to a single point with a weight that tells the number of oranges, and similarly for all apples of a bag; or map the whole bag to a single point for which we define an “apple-measure”, and an “orange-measure”. Now we apply the Ham sandwich theorem to obtain a balanced cut (there are different variants of this theorem, we choose the one suitable for our representation). If any “bags” are cut by the obtained line, we move them to the side which has less bags. This gives a valid solution.

Exercises:

  • Prove the following more general statement. Which proof technique is suitable?
    Given \( n\) bags that contain \( f\) kinds of fruits, we can select \( \lceil \frac{n+f-1}{2} \rceil \) bags that contain at least half of all kinds of fruits.
  • Prove the following variant. Which proof technique is suitable?
  • Given 100 bags that contain apples and oranges, we can select 34 bags that contain at least one third of the apples and one third of the oranges.

  • Find a general statement with \(n\) bags, \(f\) kinds of fruits and finding a subset of the bags that contains at least a \(p\)-fraction of the fruits of each kind, for arbitrary \( 0 \le p \le 1\).
  • Assume that we know the contents of each bag. Which proof leads to an efficient algorithm for finding a good subset of bags in the sense described above? In particular, which proof leads to a linear time \(( O(n) )\) algorithm?
  • Can you come up with new proofs for the puzzle? If so, I would love to hear them. Do any of the proofs admit new generalizations?

Thanks to David Futer, Lavinia Dinu, Manuel Arora, and Tobias Mömke for interesting discussions about this puzzle.

Disk intersection game

Here’s a small puzzle/game that I made, using a simple geometric concept. You can try it here: disk intersection game. The game idea is loosely inspired by the game planarity, but it is also significantly different.

disk game screenshot

There are some disks, and you can move them around arbitrarily (drag with the mouse). The goal is to make all of them “good”. When a disk is “good”, its color turns to green. The other colors indicate different levels of “badness”, as shown in the legend to the right. With some experimentation you can probably discover what you need to do to achieve this, but here is an explanation of the idea:

There is a hidden “model”, created randomly, which you need to discover. The model determines how the disks need to be interconnected, meaning which pairs of disks have to intersect each other (overlap with each other). If you “realize” this model, by moving the disks in such a position as to intersect each other in the required way, you win the game. The colors of the disks indicate how far the current configuration is from the correct model. This is computed as follows: if a certain disk should intersect disk A and no other disks, but instead it intersects disk B and C, and it doesn’t intersect A, then its “badness” is 3, so it has the color corresponding to the number 3. In other words, “badness” shows how many errors there are due to a given disk. When the “badness” of all disks is 0, you have solved the puzzle.

If you find the color codes hard to recognize, you can click the “#” button, and the “badness” will appear as a number. You can also ask for help three times during the game. Clicking the help button will display the model that has to be realized (i.e. the connections between the disks, shown as lines). There are easy and hard games, in a hard game the model tends to be more complicated, therefore harder to discover.

Try the disk intersection game.

Remarks:

  • I came up with the idea for the game, while working on a problem related to unit disk graphs. This is the first iteration of the game, so probably the gameplay and the design could be significantly improved. If you have any suggestions, please let me know in the comments.
  • There is nothing special about disks here, maybe other intersection graphs would make more interesting (or more challenging) games.
  • One reason I wrote the game, besides wanting to try out the idea, was to get familiar with HTML5 Canvas – in the future I’d like to make another, somewhat more complex game. As this was my first encounter with Canvas, and because I wrote the game in one sitting (~3 hours), the implementation is a bit rough around the edges. Please let me know if you find any bugs or if you have suggestions.

Obstruction game

Some years ago I was reading about the game of Nim, then a bit more about the theory of impartial games, and as the rabbithole seemed to go deeper and deeper, I needed some pretext to continue. So I came up with the rules of a simple paper-pencil game that I could try to analyze with the theory that I was reading about. I never managed to fully analyze the game, but it seemed to be reasonably fun to play anyway. Later I found that some very similar games have already been described.

The rules are simple: two players take turns in marking squares on a grid (say, of size 8*8). You can only mark a square if all of its neighbors (including the diagonal neighbors) are empty. The first player unable to move loses.

More details of the game are here.

Recently, I had the pleasure of discovering a website that contains the descriptions of many paper and pencil games, most of them playable on the website against the computer. The site is maintained by David Johnson-Davies. In fact, I found out about the website from him, when he told me that he also included the game I described above. The game is filed under the name “Obstruction game” which very well describes what it is about. You can even play it against the computer. Here is the website with all the games and here is the link to the Obstruction game. There is even a description with some useful strategy-tips.

Happy playing!

Ordering cyclic graphs

Suppose there are n sports teams, some of them play each other, in each game one team wins and the other loses and in the end we want to order the teams such that if A beats B than A is before B in the order. If two teams A and B played each other multiple times but, say, A clearly dominated B, we consider as if they would have played once and A beat B. If they played each other several times and there is no clear winner, or if they played only one draw, we consider as if they would have played twice and once A won, once B.

We can represent the whole situation as a directed graph with n vertices {1, …, n} and an edge from i to j if i won against j. Clearly, there are no self-loops. If the graph has no cycles, we can efficiently compute a topological sorting of the vertices and we are done. What if the graph has cycles (two teams that played a draw, or a sequence of teams where A beat B, B beat C, …, X beat A), but we still want to output a reasonable ordering? What is a reasonable ordering?

This is the vertex ordering problem and we can formulate many different criteria. I’ll go through some variants and mention for each of them, whether they are NP-hard or polynomially solvable. It turns out that almost all of them are NP-hard, and those which are not are quite trivial (plus the topological sorting mentioned before, which is also polynomially – in fact, linearly – computable). I’ll try to refer to sources where I found some, where I didn’t find any, the result is simple enough to be considered folklore. Not all the criteria that I list are reasonable – a reasonable criterion should actually lead to the topological sorting when there are no cycles. Did I forget some sensible criteria? Let me know what you think.

The general set-up is the following: we search for a permutation f:[n] -> [n], such as to minimize or maximize some quantity as follows:

1. The first criterion is that we want to minimize/maximize some reasonable function of the number of wins and the number of losses of a team. This includes the methods used in most sport tournaments where wins and loses are worth some number of points and in the end the teams are ranked by their accumulated number of points. This criterion is easy, because we can just compute the indegree/outdegree of each vertex, compute the necessary function values and sort vertices according to it.

Now we move to some more interesting criteria.

  • We either minimize (MIN) or maximize (MAX) some quantity.
  • The quantity is either the SUM, the MAXimum, the MINimum or the COUNT of something.
  • That something is either the length of EDGEs, the length of BACK-EDGEs, or SIGNED length of EDGEs.

This gives 2*4*3=24 cases.

For example, if i->j means that there is an edge from i to j:

MIN COUNT EDGE refers to    

MAX SUM EDGE refers to    

MIN SUM BACK-EDGE refers to    

MAX MIN SIGNED-EDGE refers to     .

These are all for directed graphs, as mentioned earlier. Before starting to enumerate all these cases, let’s define the same problem for undirected graphs. For undirected graphs there are less cases, as we don’t have to consider separately any edge or back-edge or signed edge. Thus there are just 2*4=8 possibilities here.

Now let’s see what we’ve got, numbering continuously all the cases.

Undirected graphs

2. MIN SUM: This is called Minimum Linear Arrangement, a known NP-hard problem.

3. MIN MAX: This is called Minimum Bandwidth, a known NP-hard problem.

4. MIN MIN: makes no sense, it can always be 1.

5. MIN COUNT: makes no sense, it is always the number of edges.

6. MAX SUM: this is equivalent to 2. on the complement graph, therefore NP-hard.

7. MAX MAX: makes no sense, it can always be n-1.

8. MAX MIN: This is the anti-bandwidth problem, studied in literature, see here, or here (leads to paywall). It is NP-hard. This can be seen via the following reduction: “Does G have a Hamiltonian path?” is the same as “can the vertices of G be arranged such that there are edges between neighbors?” is the same as “can the vertices of G be arranged such that the complement of G has anti-bandwith at least 2?”. If we could answer the last question efficiently, we could answer the first.

9. MAX COUNT: makes no sense, it is always the number of edges.

Now we move on to the original question:

Directed graphs

10. MIN SUM EDGE: NP-hard. From 2. if we replace every undirected edge with a directed edge.

11. MIN SUM BACK-EDGE: NP-hard. From 2. if we replace every undirected edge with two directed edges.

12. MIN SUM SIGNED-EDGE: this is quite interesting. Notice that we can replace a path a->b->c with a single edge a->c without changing the sum. If we do this sufficiently many times we will be left with vertices with only incoming or only outgoing edges. To minimize the sum we clearly have to put vertices with outgoing edges first, then vertices with incoming edges. Otherwise we could make a simple replacement that would decrease the sum. Furthermore, vertices with outgoing edges have to be ordered in decreasing order of degree, vertices with incoming edges ordered in increasing order of degree. Again, otherwise, a simple swap would decrease the sum. That’s all.. Observe that what we’ve got is the same as ordering the original vertices in decreasing order of [outderee-indegree]. In this sense, this is a special case of 1.

13. MAX SUM EDGE: NP-hard. From 6. if we replace every edge with a directed edge.

14. MAX SUM BACK-EDGE: NP-hard. From 6. if we replace every edge with two directed edges.

15. MAX SUM SIGNED-EDGE: solution is the reverse order of 12.

16. MIN MAX EDGE: NP-hard. From 3. if we replace every undirected edge with a directed edge.

17. MIN MAX BACK-EDGE: NP-hard. From 3. if we replace every undirected edge with two directed edges.

18. MIN MAX SIGNED-EDGE: NP-hard. From 3. if we replace every undirected edge with two directed edges. Known as Minimum Directed Bandwidth.

19. MAX MAX EDGE: makes no sense, it can always be n-1.

20. MAX MAX BACK-EDGE: makes no sense, it can always be n-1.

21. MAX MAX SIGNED-EDGE: makes no sense, it can always be n-1.

22. MIN MIN EDGE: makes no sense, it can always be 1.

23. MIN MIN BACK-EDGE: makes no sense, it can always be 1 and has to be at least 1 if there are cycles.

24. MIN MIN SIGNED-EDGE: makes no sense, it can always be -(n-1).

25. MAX MIN EDGE: NP-hard. From 8. if we replace every undirected edge with a directed edge.

26. MAX MIN BACK-EDGE: NP-hard. From 8. if we replace every undirected edge with two directed edges.

27. MAX MIN SIGNED-EDGE: NP-hard. From 8. if we replace every undirected edge with two directed edges.

28. MIN COUNT EDGE: makes no sense, it is always the number of edges.

29. MIN COUNT BACK-EDGE: NP-hard, known as Minimum Feedback Arc Set.

30. MIN COUNT SIGNED-EDGE: makes no sense, it is always the number of edges.

31. MAX COUNT EDGE: makes no sense, it is always the number of edges.

32. MAX COUNT BACK-EDGE: NP-hard, it is the reverse order of 29.

33. MAX COUNT SIGNED-EDGE: makes no sense, it is always the number of edges.

Phew :) Did I forget any interesting criteria?

From the point of view of the original motivation (a ranking of teams) the criteria that seem to some extent reasonable are: 11, 12, 17, 18, 29.

Self-counting sentences II

Let’s revisit the topic of the previous post on self-counting sentences. We looked at sentences like this:

In this sentence the number of occurrences of 1 is __, of 2 is __, ..., of n is __.

Let’s go up one more step on the ladder of abstraction, to arrive at sentences of the type:

In this sentence, there are 3 numbers appearing 1 time, 1 number appearing 2 times, 1 number appearing 3 times, 0 numbers appearing 4 times.

In this sentence, there are 2 numbers appearing 1 time, 3 numbers appearing 2 times, 0 numbers appearing 3 times, 0 numbers appearing 4 time.

Observe, that both say the truth about themselves. Below are three puzzles. In all cases the task is to fill in the gaps such as to make the sentence say the truth and the questions are: for what values of n does a solution exist and what are the solutions (if they exist).

In this sentence there are __ numbers occurring 1 time, __ numbers occurring 2 times, ..., __ numbers occurring n times.

In this sentence, from the numbers 0,1, ..., n-1, there are __ numbers occurring underlined 0 time, __ numbers occurring underlined 1 time, ..., __ numbers occurring underlined n-1 times.

In this sentence there are __ numbers occurring underlined 1 time, __ numbers occurring underlined 2 times, ..., __ numbers occurring underlined n times.

Note: I submitted the first variant of the problem to Kömal, where it appeared in the 2013 September issue (Hungarian, English – unfortunately, as of this writing, the English version appears mistaken there). Later, Toshihiro Shimizu pointed out that a formulation essentially equivalent to the second variant above appeared earlier as an IMO problem (Combinatorics 5)

.

.

.

.

.

.

The second problem is equivalent to the first problem. There exists a solution to problem 1, if and only if the same sequence of numbers is a solution to problem 2 (note that in problem 2 the counting starts from 0). Therefore we only look at the first and the third problems.

Solution of problem 1:

For small values of n, we can find the solutions by trial and error or with a small program. We denote the numbers of the solution as f(1), f(2), …, f(n).

For n=1, there is a single solution: f(1)=2.

For n=2, there is a single solution: f(1)=4, f(2)=0.

For n=3, there is a single solution: f(1)=4, f(2)=1, f(3)=0.

For n=4, there are two solutions (see the beginning of the post).

For n=5, n=6, there are no solutions.

For n=7, there are two solutions: f(1)=4, f(2)=3, f(3)=0, f(4)=1, f(5)=0, f(6)=0, f(7)=0, and f(1)=5, f(2)=1, f(3)=1, f(4)=1, f(5)=0, f(6)=0, f(7)=0.

For n=8, there are two solutions: f(1)=5, f(2)=2, f(3)=1, f(4)=1, f(5)=0, f(6)=0, f(7)=0, f(8)=0, and f(1)=5, f(2)=3, f(3)=0, f(4)=0, f(5)=1, f(6)=0, f(7)=0, f(8)=0.

For every n>=9 there are exactly three solutions:
a) f(1)=n-3, f(2)=3, f(n-3)=1, and the remaining values 0,
b) f(1)=n-2, f(2)=1, f(4)=1, f(n-4)=1, and the remaining values 0,
c) f(1)=n-3, f(2)=2, f(3)=1, f(n-4)=1, and the remaining values 0.

These solutions clearly work. Let’s prove that no other solutions exist.

We can observe two properties of the sequence f(i):

Property 1: ∑ i * f(i) = 2n. (where i goes from 1 to n)
Proof:
There are 2n numbers in the sentence and each i*f(i) term counts how many numbers are there with multiplicity i. To have a multiplicity greater than n would mean that all gaps are filled with the same value, which cannot yield a true sentence for any value. Thus the possible multiplicities are between 1 and n, therefore ∑ i * f(i) gives the total number of numbers in the sentence, which is 2n.

Property 2: ∑ f(i) = n+1. (where i goes from 1 to n)
Proof:
Clearly, for all i, f(i)>=0 and f(i)<=n. If for all i, f(i)>0 would hold, ∑ i * f(i) would be larger than 2n, violating Property 1. Therefore, some of the f(i) values have to be equal to 0, which means that all numbers 0,1,…,n appear in the sentence. Furthermore, all numbers that appear in the sentence have multiplicity between 1 and n. Thus, ∑ f(i) gives the total number of distinct values, which is n+1.

Now we prove that a) b) c) are the only solutions for n>=9.

If f(1)>n-2,
it must be that f(1)=n-1, but now n-1 occurs twice, so to maintain that n-1 values occur once, we need to write n-1 in every other position as well. This is not a correct solution.

If f(1)=n-2,
we must have exactly one other nonzero value (besides n-2) written in the gaps. We cannot write n-2 anywhere else, as that would violate Property 2. To get a sum of n+1, the possibilities are writing one time 3, or three times 1. Writing 3 anywhere doesn’t make the sentence correct, so it remains to write three 1’s. But then the number of 0’s will be n-4, the number of 1’s will be 4 and the number of (n-2)’s will be 2. This gives us solution b).

If f(1)=n-3,
we have two other nonzero values (besides n-3) written in the gaps. They also have to add up to 4 (Property 2). That can be as 3+1 or as 2+1+1. The first case means that 1,3 and n-3 have multiplicities 2 and 0 has multiplicity n-3. The second case means that 2 and n-3 have multiplicity 2, 0 has multiplicity n-4 and 1 has multiplicity 3. These cases uniquely lead to solutions a) and c).

If f(1)<n-3,
suppose f(1)=n-k (where k>3). The value 0 has to appear more than one time (otherwise the sum of Property 1 would be too large). Therefore, among the values 1, …, n, there are k distinct values which are written somewhere in the gaps (to make their multiplicities larger than one in the whole sentence). We know that n-k appears in the first gap, so we have k-1 other values in the gaps starting from the second. Let’s denote these values by a1 < a2 < . . .  < ak − 1. Since they are written in the gaps after the first one, it follows that there are at least a1 + a2 + . . .  + ak − 1 distinct numbers that appear more than once in the sentence. Even if one of them is n-k, and one of them is 0, that still leaves S = a1 + a2 + . . .  + ak − 1 − 2 distinct numbers appearing more than once (therefore, also in the gaps). Since a1 ≥ 1, we have S >= k(k-1)/2 – 2. Even if the smallest of these numbers is 1, we get that f(i) >> n+1, for k>3. This violates Property 2, therefore no solution of this kind is possible.

Solution of problem 3:

For n=1, we have f(1)=1, unique solution.
For n=2, we have f(1)=2, f(2)=0, unique solution.
For n=3, we have f(1)=1, f(2)=1, f(3)=0, unique solution.
For n=4, we have f(1)=2, f(2)=1, f(3)=0, f(4)=0, unique solution.

For n>=5, we have exactly two solutions:
a) f(2)=1, f(n-2)=1, the remaining values 0
b) f(1)=2, f(n-2)=1, the remaining values 0.

Proof:

Similarly to the first problem, now we have the property:
∑ i * f(i) = n.

Clearly f(n)=0, otherwise all values would have to be equal, which is not a correct solution.
Also, f(n-1)=0. The only alternative would be f(n-1)=1, and all other values equal to zero, but this is not a correct solution either.

If f(n-2)=1 we need that ∑ i * f(i) over all other values is 2. This leads to solutions a) and b) only.
f(n-2)>=2 is not possible, as it would violate the property for n>=5.

Now suppose f(n-k) is the last nonzero value, for k>=3. This means that there are k numbers that are not equal to one of the most frequent values. If 0 is one of the most frequent values, then there are k nonzero values. All of them cannot be equal to 1, as that would not be a correct solution, so ∑ i * f(i) >= k(k-1)/2 + n-k + 1, which is larger than n for k>=3, violating the required property. On the other hand, if less than half of the elements are 0, the property is clearly violated, which shows that there are no other solutions.

Self-counting sentences

In this sentence the number of occurrences of 1 is 2, of 2 is 3, of 3 is 2, of 4 is 1.

This self-referential, true sentence is a variant of a puzzle attributed to the logician Raphael Robinson, popularized in Douglas Hofstadter’s book Metamagical Themas. In the book the puzzle appears in the following form:

Fill in the gaps such as to make the sentence true:

In this sentence the number of occurrences of the digit 0 is __, of digit 1 is __, of digit 2 is __, ..., of digit 9 is __.

With some trial and error you can find two different solutions, and it has been shown that no other solutions are possible. The problem has also been studied using some theory from the field of dynamical systems. Here are two interesting links, both containing the solution of the puzzle.

In this post, however, I would like to look at a slightly different puzzle. Instead of counting digits, I am counting the numbers as indivisible units. If, for instance, “15” appears in the sentence, I count it as “15”, not as one “1” and one “5”. In this way the problem is independent of the base in which the numbers are represented.

In both of the following two puzzles the task is to fill in the gaps such as to make the sentences true. In the first sentence the values can be between 1 and n (including 1 and n), in the second sentence the values can be between 0 and n-1 (both included). For what values of n are the problems solvable? How many solutions are there?

In this sentence the number of occurrences of 1 is __, of 2 is __, ..., of n is __.

In this sentence the number of underlined occurrences of 0 is __, of 1 is __, of 2 is __, ..., of n-1 is __.

Think about the puzzles for some time, or scroll down for the solution. Let me know if you find a simpler solution. I also wrote a follow-up post, with a different variant of the problem.

.

.

.

.

.

.

It can be shown that the two problems are equivalent: let’s denote the numbers written in the gaps of the first sentence by f(1), …, f(n). It can be seen easily that f(1), …, f(n) form a solution for the first problem if and only if f(1)-1, …, f(n)-1 form a solution for the second problem. So it’s enough to look at the first puzzle only.

With some case-based analysis we can show that there is no solution for the cases n=1, n=2, n=3 and n=6.
For n=4, there are two solutions, the one given in the beginning of the post and the following: f(1)=3, f(2)=1, f(3)=3, f(4)=1.

For n=5, the solution is given by the sequence: f(1)=3, f(2)=2, f(3)=3, f(4)=1, f(5)=1 and it is unique. These can be verified manually.

For every n>=7, there is a solution, given by f(1)=n-3, f(2)=3, f(3)=2, f(n-3)=2, and f(k)=1, for every k other than 1,2,3, and n-3. Let’s prove that this is the only solution:

Suppose there is some other solution.
If f(1)=n-3, then f(n-3)>=2.
—> If f(n-3)=2, then we need f(2)>=3.
——> If f(2)=3, then we get the same solution.
——> If f(2)>3, then there exist distinct x and y (also different from n-3, 1 and 2), for which f(x)=f(y)=2, so we have a value different from 1 at places 1,2,x,y,n-3, which means that we don’t have enough places to put 1’s, to satisfy f(1)=n-3.
—> If f(n-3)>2, then we have some x (different from 1 and n-3), for which f(x)=n-3. But then there are n-4 places where we need to put x, again not leaving enough places to satisfy f(1)=n-3.

If f(1)>n-3, then f(f(1))>=2.
—> If f(f(1))=2, then we need f(2)>=3 and f(f(2))>=2. We ran out of places for 1’s, since 1,2,f(2) and f(1) are distinct and they map to values different from 1.
—> If f(f(1))>2, then there is some x (other than 1) with f(x)=f(1)>=n-2, which means that we need to fill at least n-3 places with the value x, not leaving enough place for the 1’s.

The interesting case remains when f(1)<n-3. This condition means that in at least 5 places we need to write a number different from 1.
Suppose there are exactly k places, corresponding to the indices x1, …, xk, where we have an entry different from 1. This means that f(x1), …, f(xk) are different from 1 and k>=5. Let x1=1, since we know that in place 1 we have an entry different from 1.

Observe that among f(x1), …, f(xk) there have to be exactly k-1 distinct elements. This is because we need a value different from 1 in all places 1, f(x1), …, f(xk), and unless there are exactly k such places, we reached a contradiction. Since we have k-1 distinct elements all different from 1, the maximum among them is at least k and the second largest element is at least k-1. This means that there is a number t different from 1, such that f(t)>=k-1, therefore, t appears as a count in at least k-2 places. If out of k counts we have k-2 equal, we cannot have k-1 distinct values, so we reached a blatant contradiction. Therefore this case is impossible and the solution given above is unique.

Mixed metaphors

“Verdi is the Puccini of music” – this quip attributed to the composer Igor Stravinsky appears in Douglas Hofstadter’s book Metamagical Themas. In a similar vein he adds: “The knee is the Achilles’ heel of the leg”. A well-known humorist, probably inspired by the first sentence, uses the line “Beethoven is the Mozart of classical music”. Looking at a lavishly decorated building, we might say “It seems that Baroque has a renaissance”.

What is common in these humorous and somewhat faulty metaphors? Is there a name for this phenomenon? Are there other good examples?

To explain the obvious, suppose we are using analogies or metaphors of the form “X is Y”, where Y is the “source”, whose attributes we borrow, ascribing them to the “target” X. In this set-up, Y seems to play two roles: one concrete, immediate and one abstract, idealized. In the case of Mozart, the concrete role is that of the 18th century composer, while the abstract role is something along “a widely celebrated, brilliant and prolific, classical master of a genre”. Renaissance is the cultural movement started in Europe in the 14th century, but also the revival of a style, in the case of Renaissance itself, mostly of the classical Greek and Roman. Never mind that in this case the capitalization of the word betrays which meaning we are referring to.

The trick for the faulty metaphor to work (or in this case, for it not to work, i.e. to sound broken and to generate tension and/or humor), seems to hinge on our ability to move back and forth between the two roles, the concrete and the abstract. Furthermore, it is necessary that the analogy is understandable, in other words, that the abstract meaning is well established. In fact, the more overused the metaphor, the better it is for comical effect. The “Achilles’ heel of something” clearly fulfills this requirement. Still, “Shakespeare is the Mozart of English literature” and “Stone-washed jeans are having a renaissance” would be perfectly valid, if not very interesting analogies. To produce the effect we are looking for, we need one more ingredient: if we denote by Y1 and Y2 the concrete, resp. the abstract meanings of the source, we should choose Y in such a way that “X is Y2″ sounds fine, but X and Y1 are somehow clashing, for example, by being members of the same category, or by being downright contradictory. In this way, shifting to the “X is Y1″ meaning feels like falling into a trap.

Since there already exist snowclones, malapropisms, solecisms, contronyms, garden path sentences, it seems unfair that such a clearly delimited phenomenon does not have its own name. Can you suggest one? The examples above are all, in some sense, mixed metaphors, but the mixing happens in a well defined way. What would be a good neologism for metaphors broken in this particular way?

Here are some more examples that loosely fit the same structural pattern, although they are not necessarily funny. Please, let me know, if you can think of more!

  • The queen is the king of chess pieces.
  • The Russian campaign was Napoleon’s Waterloo moment.
  • The lizard you keep in the kitchen has become the elephant in the living room in our relationship.
  • The gold plating is the crown jewel of that necklace.
  • The bald eagle is the canary in the coal mine of the ecosystem.
  • The 700 pound gorilla that escaped the zoo is the 800 pound gorilla.
  • That blue whale has become his white whale.
  • The new fighter jet is the flagship of the army.
  • “Raincoat” is an umbrella term for many different products.
  • Alexander the Great solved the Gordian knot of defeating the Persian army.
  • Theseus performed the herculean task of killing the Minotaur.
  • Euro cents are a dime a dozen.
  • Luxembourg is the Switzerland of Europe.
  • A blue swan would be a black swan.
  • A notebook is a textbook example of a stationery product.
  • Latin was the lingua franca of medieval Europe.
  • The cerebrospinal fluid is the lifeblood of the organism.
  • John Smith is the John Doe of English names.
  • Saab is Sweden’s answer to the Volvo.

EDIT:

  • From niklasni1, over at reddit:
    • Humans are the tortoises of the animal kingdom.
  • Noah suggests the term Locaphor. Like it!
  • Another one, similar to some of the above:
    • By crossing the Po, Caesar crossed the Rubicon.
  • cnan1u adds:
    • Copper is the gold standard of electric wires.
  • cnan1u also adds the following:
    • Tobacco is the smoking gun of lung cancer.
    • Women are the founding fathers of feminism.
    • Bison were the bread and butter of early humans.
    • The SI unit is the yardstick of measurement.
    • Espresso is the barista’s cup of tea.

    and many more. Thanks!

  • Turns out that Richard Lederer’s book “Anguished English” has some more examples in its chapters “Mixed-Up Metaphors” and “Goldwynisms and Berraisms”.

Bongard problems

Bongard problems are a type of puzzle invented by Russian computer scientist M. M. Bongard, intended as challenges for pattern recognition algorithms. Regardless of the possible relevance to computer science, they are much fun simply as puzzles created by people for other people to solve. They were popularized in the Gödel, Escher, Bach book and Hofstadter himself designed many Bongard problems. Harry Foundalis has several pages dedicated to these problems, with an extensive index of example Bongard problems.

The idea of a Bongard problem is the following: given a set A of six figures (examples) and another set B of six figures (counter-examples), discover what is the rule that the figures in A obey and figures in B violate.

Here are some very nice examples of varying difficulty and a much more detailed description:
http://www.foundalis.com/res/diss_research.html

Inspired by these examples I tried my hand at making some Bongard puzzles myself. The modest result is below. If you can solve them, leave the answer in the comments.

Puzzle 1.

Puzzle 2.

Puzzle 3.

Puzzle 4.

solutions